green numbers give full details.     |    back to list of philosophers     |     unexpand these ideas

Ideas of Kent Bach, by Text

[American, fl. 1985, Professor at San Francisco State University.]

2005 The Emperor's New 'Knows'
I p.56 How could 'S knows he has hands' not have a fixed content?
     Full Idea: How can it be that a sentence like 'George knows that he has hands', even with time and references fixed, does not have a fixed propositional content?
     From: Kent Bach (The Emperor's New 'Knows' [2005], I)
     A reaction: The appeal is to G.E. Moore's common sense view of immediate knowledge (Idea 6349). The reply is simply that the word 'knows' shifts its meaning, having high standards in sceptical philosophy classes, and low standards on the street.
I p.61 If contextualism is right, knowledge sentences are baffling out of their context
     Full Idea: Contextualism seems to predict that if you encounter a knowledge attribution out of context you won't be in a position to grasp which proposition the sentence expresses.
     From: Kent Bach (The Emperor's New 'Knows' [2005], I)
     A reaction: It is only the word 'knows' which is at issue in the sentence. If someone is said to 'know' about the world of the fairies, we might well be puzzled as to what proposition was being expressed. Is the word 'flat' baffling out of context?
III p.68 Sceptics aren't changing the meaning of 'know', but claiming knowing is tougher than we think
     Full Idea: When a sceptic brings up far-fetched possibilities and argues that we can't rule them out, he is not raising the standard for the word 'know'. He is showing it is tougher than we realise for a belief to qualify as normal knowledge at all.
     From: Kent Bach (The Emperor's New 'Knows' [2005], III)
     A reaction: [Bach cites Richard Feldman for this idea] I think that what happens in the contextual account is that 'true', 'belief' and 'know' retain their standard meaning, and it is 'justified' which shifts. 'I am fully justified' can have VERY different meanings!
2006 What Does It Take to Refer?
Intro p.517 What refers: indefinite or definite or demonstrative descriptions, names, indexicals, demonstratives?
     Full Idea: Philosophers agree that some expressions refer, but disagree over which ones. Few include indefinite descriptions, but some include definite descriptions, or only demonstrative descriptions. Some like proper names, some only indexicals and demonstratives.
     From: Kent Bach (What Does It Take to Refer? [2006], Intro)
     A reaction: My initial prejudice is rather Strawsonian - that people refer, not language, and it can be done in all sorts of ways. But Bach argues well that only language intrinsically does it. Even pointing fails without linguistic support.
Intro p.519 An object can be described without being referred to
     Full Idea: An object can be described without being referred to.
     From: Kent Bach (What Does It Take to Refer? [2006], Intro)
     A reaction: I'm not clear how this is possible for a well-known object, though it is clearly possible for a speculative object, such as a gadget I would like to buy. In the former case reference seems to occur even if the speaker is trying to avoid it.
22.1 p.519 If we can refer to things which change, we can't be obliged to single out their properties
     Full Idea: We can refer to things which change over time, which suggests that in thinking of and in referring to an individual we are not constrained to represent it as that which has certain properties.
     From: Kent Bach (What Does It Take to Refer? [2006], 22.1)
     A reaction: This seems a good argument against the descriptive theory of reference which is not (I think) in Kripke. Problems like vagueness and the Ship of Theseus rear their heads.
22.1 p.534 Fictional reference is different inside and outside the fiction
     Full Idea: We must distinguish 'reference' in a fiction from reference outside the fiction to fictional entities.
     From: Kent Bach (What Does It Take to Refer? [2006], 22.1)
     A reaction: This may be more semantically than ontologically significant. It is perhaps best explicated by Coleridge's distinction over whether or not I am 'suspending my disbelief' when I am discussing a character.
22.1 p.534 We can refer to fictional entities if they are abstract objects
     Full Idea: If fictional entities, such as characters in a play, are real, albeit abstract entities, then we can genuinely refer to them.
     From: Kent Bach (What Does It Take to Refer? [2006], 22.1)
     A reaction: [He cites Nathan Salmon 1998] Personally I would prefer to say that abstract entities are fictions. Fictional characters have uncertain identity conditions. Do they all have a pancreas, if this is never mentioned?
22.1 s1 p.522 We can think of an individual without have a uniquely characterizing description
     Full Idea: Being able to think of an individual does not require being able to identify that individual by means of a uniquely characterizing description.
     From: Kent Bach (What Does It Take to Refer? [2006], 22.1 s1)
     A reaction: There is a bit of an equivocation over 'recognise' here. His example is 'the first child born in the 4th century'. We can't visually recognise such people, but the description does fix them, and a records office might give us 'recognition'.
22.1 s2 p.523 You 'allude to', not 'refer to', an individual if you keep their identity vague
     Full Idea: If you say 'a special person is coming to visit', you are not referring to but merely 'alluding to' that individual. This does not count as referring because you are not expressing a singular proposition about it.
     From: Kent Bach (What Does It Take to Refer? [2006], 22.1 s2)
     A reaction: If you add 'I hope he doesn't wear his red suit, but I hope he plays his tuba', you seem to be expressing singular propositions about the person. Bach seems to want a very strict notion of reference, as really attaching listeners to individuals.
22.1 s5 p.526 Definite descriptions can be used to refer, but are not semantically referential
     Full Idea: If Russell is, as I believe, basically right, then definite descriptions are the paradigm of singular terms that can be used to refer but are not linguistically (semantically) referential.
     From: Kent Bach (What Does It Take to Refer? [2006], 22.1 s5)
     A reaction: I'm not sure that we can decide what is 'semantically referential'. Most of the things we refer to don't have names. We don't then 'use' definite descriptions (I'm thinking) - they actually DO the job. If we use them, we can 'use' names too?
22.1 s7 p.529 It can't be real reference if it could refer to some other thing that satisfies the description
     Full Idea: If one is referring to whatever happens to satisfy a description, and one would be referring to something else were it to have satisfied the description instead, this is known as 'weak' reference,...but surely this is not reference at all.
     From: Kent Bach (What Does It Take to Refer? [2006], 22.1 s7)
     A reaction: Bach wants a precise notion of reference, as success in getting the audience to focus on the correct object. He talks of this case as 'singling out' some unfixed thing, and he also has 'alluding to' an unstated thing. Plausible view.
22.2 L1 p.538 Free logic at least allows empty names, but struggles to express non-existence
     Full Idea: Unlike standard first-order logic, free logic can allow empty names, but still has to deny existence by either representing it as a predicate, or invoke some dubious distinction such as between existence and being.
     From: Kent Bach (What Does It Take to Refer? [2006], 22.2 L1)
22.2 L1 p.538 In first-order we can't just assert existence, and it is very hard to deny something's existence
     Full Idea: In standard logic we can't straightforwardly say that n exists. We have to resort to using a formula like '∃x(x=n)', but we can't deny n's existence by negating that formula, because standard first-order logic disallows empty names.
     From: Kent Bach (What Does It Take to Refer? [2006], 22.2 L1)
22.2 L1 p.538 In logic constants play the role of proper names
     Full Idea: In standard first-order logic the role of proper names is played by individual constants.
     From: Kent Bach (What Does It Take to Refer? [2006], 22.2 L1)
22.2 L1 p.538 Millian names struggle with existence, empty names, identities and attitude ascription
     Full Idea: The familiar problems with the Millian view of names are the problem of positive and negative existential statements, empty names, identity sentences, and propositional attitude ascription.
     From: Kent Bach (What Does It Take to Refer? [2006], 22.2 L1)
     A reaction: I take this combination of problems to make an overwhelming case against the daft idea that the semantics of a name amounts to the actual object it picks out. It is a category mistake to attempt to insert a person into a sentence.
22.2 L1 p.538 Proper names can be non-referential - even predicate as well as attributive uses
     Full Idea: Like it or not, proper names have non-referential uses, including not only attributive but even predicate uses.
     From: Kent Bach (What Does It Take to Refer? [2006], 22.2 L1)
     A reaction: 'He's a right little Hitler'. 'You're doing a George Bush again'. 'Try to live up to the name of Churchill'.
22.2 L2 p.542 Since most expressions can be used non-referentially, none of them are inherently referential
     Full Idea: An embarrassingly simple argument is that most expressions can be used literally but not referentially, no variation in meaning explains this fact, so its meaning is compatible with being non-referential, so no expression is inherently referential.
     From: Kent Bach (What Does It Take to Refer? [2006], 22.2 L2)
     A reaction: I think I have decided that no expression is 'inherently referential', and that it is all pragmatics.
22.2 L3 p.543 People slide from contextual variability all the way to contextual determination
     Full Idea: People slide from contextual variability to context relativity to context sensitivity to context dependence to contextual determination.
     From: Kent Bach (What Does It Take to Refer? [2006], 22.2 L3)
     A reaction: This is reminiscent of the epistemological slide from cultural or individual relativity of some observed things, to a huge metaphysical denial of truth. Bach's warning applies to me, as I have been drifting down his slope lately. Nice.
22.2 L3 p.544 Context does not create reference; it is just something speakers can exploit
     Full Idea: Context does not determine or constitute reference; rather, it is something for the speaker to exploit to enable the listener to determine the intended reference.
     From: Kent Bach (What Does It Take to Refer? [2006], 22.2 L3)
     A reaction: Bach thinks linguistic reference is a matter of speaker's intentions, and I think he is right. And this idea is right too. The domain of quantification constantly shifts in a conversation, and good speakers and listeners are sensitive to this.
22.2 L3 p.545 'That duck' may not refer to the most obvious one in the group
     Full Idea: If one ducks starts quacking furiously, and you say 'that duck is excited', it isn't context that makes me take it that you are referring to the quacking duck. You could be referring to a quiet duck you recognise by its distinctive colour.
     From: Kent Bach (What Does It Take to Refer? [2006], 22.2 L3)
     A reaction: A persuasive example to make his point against the significance of context in conversational reference. Speaker's intended reference must always trump any apparent reference suggested by context.
22.2 L4 p.546 What a pronoun like 'he' refers back to is usually a matter of speaker's intentions
     Full Idea: To illustrate speakers' intentions, consider the anaphoric reference using pronouns in these: "A cop arrested a robber; he was wearing a badge", and "A cop arrested a robber; he was wearing a mask". The natural supposition is not the inevitable one.
     From: Kent Bach (What Does It Take to Refer? [2006], 22.2 L4)
     A reaction: I am a convert to speakers' intentions as the source of all reference, and this example seems to illustrate it very well. 'He said..' 'Who said?'
22.2 L4 p.549 Information comes from knowing who is speaking, not just from interpretation of the utterance
     Full Idea: It is a fallacy that all the information in an utterance must come from its interpretation, which ignores the essentially pragmatic fact that the speaker is making the utterance.
     From: Kent Bach (What Does It Take to Refer? [2006], 22.2 L4)
     A reaction: [He cites Barwise and Perry 1983:34] This is blatantly obvious in indexical remarks like 'I am tired', where the words don't tell you who is tired. But also 'the car has broken down, dear'.
22.3 p.551 Just alluding to or describing an object is not the same as referring to it
     Full Idea: Much of what speakers do that passes for referring is merely alluding or describing. ...It is one thing for a speaker to express a thought about a certain object using an expression, and quite another for the expression to stand for that object.
     From: Kent Bach (What Does It Take to Refer? [2006], 22.3)
     A reaction: Bach builds up a persuasive case for this view. If the question, though, is 'what are you talking about?', then saying what is being alluded to or singled out or described seems fine. Bach is being rather stipulative.