Ideas from 'Dispositions' by Stephen Mumford [1998], by Theme Structure

[found in 'Dispositions' by Mumford,Stephen [OUP 1998,978-0-19-925982-3]].

green numbers give full details    |     back to texts     |     unexpand these ideas


7. Existence / D. Theories of Reality / 2. Realism
Modest realism says there is a reality; the presumptuous view says we can accurately describe it
                        Full Idea: The claim of modest realism is that there is a subject-independent reality; the presumptuous claim is that we are capable of describing that reality accurately.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 09.1)
                        A reaction: And the super-presumptuous claim is that there only exists one ultimate accurate description of reality. I am happy to call myself a Modest Realist on this one.
7. Existence / D. Theories of Reality / 4. Anti-realism
Anti-realists deny truth-values to all statements, and say evidence and ontology are inseparable
                        Full Idea: The anti-realist declines to permit that all statements have truth-values. ...The essence of the anti-realist position is that evidence and ontology cannot be separated.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 03.6)
                        A reaction: [second half on p.51] The idea that evidence and ontology are 'inseparable' strikes me as an absurd idea. The proposal that you should not speculate about ontology without some sort of evidence is, of course, not unreasonable.
8. Modes of Existence / B. Properties / 3. Types of Properties
Dispositions and categorical properties are two modes of presentation of the same thing
                        Full Idea: The dispositional and the categorical are correctly understood just as two modes of presentation of the same instantiated properties.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 08.6)
                        A reaction: This is Mumford's own conclusion, after discussing the views of Armstrong. How about 'a disposition is the modal profile' of a categorical property?
8. Modes of Existence / B. Properties / 6. Categorical Properties
Categorical predicates are those unconnected to functions
                        Full Idea: A predicate which is conceptually connected to no function ... is a categorical predicate.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 09.7)
                        A reaction: This is an expansion of Mumford's own theory of dispositions, as functional. Does a cork in a wine bottle have a function, but without doing anything? It seems to achieve its function purely through its structure.
Categorical properties and dispositions appear to explain one another
                        Full Idea: Though categorical properties provide explanations for dispositions, categorical properties are also explained by dispositions; hence neither category uniquely explains the other.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 05.3)
                        A reaction: The conclusion doesn't seem to follow. It depends which one is found at the bottom level. It can go up from a basic disposition, to a categorical property, to another disposition - or the other way around.
There are four reasons for seeing categorical properties as the most fundamental
                        Full Idea: Four reasons for reducing everything to the categorical are: categorical predicates have wider scope; dispositions are variably realised by the categorical; categorical is 1st order, dispositions 2nd; categorical properties are explanatorily basic.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 08.5)
                        A reaction: I particularly reject the fourth reason, as I take categorical properties as still in need of explanation. The categorical view is contingent (and Humean), but I take the categorical properties to be necessitated by the underlying powers.
8. Modes of Existence / B. Properties / 7. Emergent Properties
A lead molecule is not leaden, and macroscopic properties need not be microscopically present
                        Full Idea: Though lead is said to be composed of molecules of lead, these molecules are not leaden in the everyday sense of the word. This suggests that a property need not be present at the microscopic level in order to be present at the macroscopic level.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 02.3)
                        A reaction: [He quotes Joske] This strikes me as a key principle to grasp about properties. One H2O molecule is not water, any more than a brick is a house! Nearly all properties (or all?) are 'emergent' (in the sensible, non-mystical use of that word).
8. Modes of Existence / C. Powers and Dispositions / 2. Powers as Basic
Dispositions are attacked as mere regularities of events, or place-holders for unknown properties
                        Full Idea: Dispositions are attacked as either just saying how something will behave (logical fictions about regularities of events), or as primitive pre-scientific terms like 'phlogiston', place-holders used when we are ignorant of real properties.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 01.1)
                        A reaction: [compressed] The first view he calls the Ryle-Wittgenstein view, which seems to track back to Hume.
8. Modes of Existence / C. Powers and Dispositions / 3. Powers as Derived
I say the categorical base causes the disposition manifestation
                        Full Idea: The view I promote is one where the categorical base is a cause of the disposition manifestation.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 05.5)
                        A reaction: It seems to me (I think) that the most basic thing has to be a power, whose nature is intrinsically beyond our grasp, and that categorical properties are the result of these powers. Powers are dispositional in character.
If dispositions have several categorical realisations, that makes the two separate
                        Full Idea: We might claim that dispositions are variably realized by a number of categorical bases; therefore they must be distinct from those bases.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 05.4)
                        A reaction: Cars can be realised by a variety of models, therefore models are not cars? This might work if dispositions are only characterised functionally, as Mumford proposes, but I'm not convinced.
Dispositions are classifications of properties by functional role
                        Full Idea: A dispositional property is the classification of a property according to its functional role....[p.85] What is essential to a disposition - its identity condition - is its functional role.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 04.5)
                        A reaction: This is Mumford's view of dispositions. I am wary of any proposal to define something according to its role, because it must have an intrinsic nature which equips it to have that role.
8. Modes of Existence / C. Powers and Dispositions / 5. Powers and Properties
All properties must be causal powers (since they wouldn't exist otherwise)
                        Full Idea: It seems that every property must be a causal power, since every property must be causally potent (as a necessary condition of its very existence).
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 04.7)
                        A reaction: Mumford cautiously endorses this idea, which seems to rest on the thesis that 'to exist is to have causal powers'. I think I am even keener on it than Mumford is. Powers and properties need to be disentangled, however.
Intrinsic properties are just causal powers, and identifying a property as causal is then analytic
                        Full Idea: Understanding intrinsic properties as being causal powers is likely to be most profitable, and, if true, renders the causal criterion of property existence true analytically.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 06.2)
                        A reaction: [He cites E.Fales on this] I'm inclined to think that in the ultimate ontology the notion of a 'property' drops out. There are true causal powers, and then conventional human ways of grouping such powers together and naming them.
8. Modes of Existence / C. Powers and Dispositions / 6. Dispositions / a. Dispositions
Dispositions are ascribed to at least objects, substances and persons
                        Full Idea: Dispositions are ascribed to at least three distinguishable classes of things: objects, substances, and persons.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 01.1)
                        A reaction: Are dispositions not also ascribed to properties? Magnetism has a disposition to attract iron filings?
Unlike categorical bases, dispositions necessarily occupy a particular causal role
                        Full Idea: The idea of a disposition occupying a different causal role involves a conceptual confusion, ...but there is no conceptual or logical absurdity in a categorical base occupying a different causal role.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 07.3)
                        A reaction: This is the core of Mumford's theory of dispositions. I'm beginning to think that dispositions are merely ways we have of describing and labelling functional mechanisms, and so 'dispositions' drop out of the final story.
Dispositions can be contrasted either with occurrences, or with categorical properties
                        Full Idea: For some the notion of a disposition is contrasted with the notion of an occurrence; for others, it is contrasted with that of a categorical property.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 01.6)
                        A reaction: I vote for dispositions over the other two, but I take the categorical properties to be the main rival.
8. Modes of Existence / C. Powers and Dispositions / 6. Dispositions / b. Dispositions and powers
If dispositions are powers, background conditions makes it hard to say what they do
                        Full Idea: The realist says that disposition ascriptions are ascriptions of real powers. This leaves unanswered the question, 'power to do what?' The problem of background conditions means that the realist cannot say what it is that a power is a power to do.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 04.9)
                        A reaction: It is hard to say what a disposition will do, under any other account of dispositions. I would take a power to be defined by a 'modal profile', rather than an actual account of what it will lead to.
Maybe dispositions can replace powers in metaphysics, as what induces property change
                        Full Idea: Dispositions can regain the metaphysical role traditionally ascribed to real powers: the that-in-virtue-of-which-something-will-G, if F.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 06.9)
                        A reaction: The attraction is that dispositions can be specified a little more clearly (especially in Mumford's functional version) whereas there may be no more to say about a power once it has been located and named.
8. Modes of Existence / C. Powers and Dispositions / 6. Dispositions / c. Dispositions as conditional
Orthodoxy says dispositions entail conditionals (rather than being equivalent to them)
                        Full Idea: The orthodox realist view has it that what makes an ascription a disposition ascription is not that it is equivalent to a conditional proposition but that it entails one.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 04.7)
                        A reaction: Mumford says that Martin has shown that dispositions need not entail conditionals (when a 'fink' is operating, something which intervenes between disposition and outcome).
8. Modes of Existence / C. Powers and Dispositions / 6. Dispositions / e. Dispositions as potential
Dispositions are not just possibilities - they are features of actual things
                        Full Idea: Dispositions should correctly be understood as more than mere possibilities. To say something has a disposition is to say something about how it is actually.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], Pref)
                        A reaction: To me this is a basic axiom of metaphysics. The word 'power' serves well for the actual embodiment of a disposition. A power gives rise to one or more dispositions. Or one or more powers give rise to a disposition?
There could be dispositions that are never manifested
                        Full Idea: It seems plausible that a disposition could be possessed though no manifestation events occur.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 01.6)
                        A reaction: It is more than 'plausible' - it is screamingly obvious to everybody, apart from a few philosophers. "Some mute inglorious Milton here may rest" (Gray's Elegy).
8. Modes of Existence / C. Powers and Dispositions / 7. Against Powers
If every event has a cause, it is easy to invent a power to explain each case
                        Full Idea: Given any event, and the assumption that every event has a cause, then some power can always be invented as the cause of that event.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 06.6)
                        A reaction: This is a useful warning, and probably explains why 'powers' fell out of fashion in scientifice theorising. They seem to make a return, though, as an appropriate term for the bottom level of each of our explanations.
Traditional powers initiate change, but are mysterious between those changes
                        Full Idea: In the old-fashioned sense, 'powers' are real potentialities that initiate changes but seem to have a mysterious existence in between those changes.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 07.10)
                        A reaction: What is a person when they are asleep? What is a dishwasher when it isn't running? What is gunpowder when it doesn't explode? We all understand latent powers. To see them as a 'mystery' is to want to know too much.
Categorical eliminativists say there are no dispositions, just categorical states or mechanisms
                        Full Idea: The categorical eliminativist claims that there are no dispositional properties. All properties must be conceived of as categorical states or mechanisms, in the spirit of Boyle's explanation of powers.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 08.3A)
                        A reaction: What is the difference between a structure and a mechanism? How do we distinguish an active from an inactive mechanism? Without powers or dispositions, nature is dead junk.
9. Objects / D. Essence of Objects / 11. Essence of Artefacts
Many artefacts have dispositional essences, which make them what they are
                        Full Idea: Thermostats, thermometers, axes, spoons, and batteries have dispositional essences, which make them what they are.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 01.2 iv)
                        A reaction: I would have thought that we could extend this proposal well beyond artefacts, but it certainly seems particularly clear in artefacts, where a human intention seems to be inescapably involved.
10. Modality / B. Possibility / 8. Conditionals / c. Truth-function conditionals
Truth-functional conditionals can't distinguish whether they are causal or accidental
                        Full Idea: If a conditional remains truth-functional it is incapable of expressing the fact that the connection between antecedent and consequent in the conditional is a causal one rather than merely accidental
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 03.8)
                        A reaction: This is the first step towards an account of conditionals which will work in real life rather than merely in classical logic.
10. Modality / B. Possibility / 8. Conditionals / d. Non-truthfunction conditionals
Dispositions are not equivalent to stronger-than-material conditionals
                        Full Idea: The conclusion that disposition ascriptions are not equivalent to stronger-than-material conditionals is largely to be accepted.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 04.7)
                        A reaction: [he attributes the view to C.B.Martin 1994] It is hard to see how to describe a disposition in anything other than conditional terms. Mumford's 'functional role' probably has to be described conditionally. It is how the conditional cashes out.
14. Science / D. Explanation / 2. Types of Explanation / a. Types of explanation
Nomothetic explanations cite laws, and structural explanations cite mechanisms
                        Full Idea: A nomothetic explanation appeals to laws where the explanandum is shown to be an instance of a general law. ...The alternative is a structural explanation, which postulates a mechanism, opening up a hidden world.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 06.4)
                        A reaction: [He cites E.McMullin 1978] I am very much in favour of structural explanations, and opposed to nomothetic ones. That is, nomothetic accounts are only the first step towards an explanation - perhaps a mere identification of the explanandum.
14. Science / D. Explanation / 2. Types of Explanation / e. Lawlike explanations
General laws depend upon the capacities of particulars, not the other way around
                        Full Idea: Laws, qua true generalities, if they exist at all, are ontologically parasitic upon the capacities of particulars, rather than the other way round.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 10.6)
                        A reaction: Quite so. And hence trying to explain a particular behaviour by saying that it falls under a law is absurdly circular and vacuous.
14. Science / D. Explanation / 2. Types of Explanation / k. Explanations by essence
If fragile just means 'breaks when dropped', it won't explain a breakage
                        Full Idea: If fragile means nothing more than 'breaks when dropped', then it is no explanation of why something breaks when dropped.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 06.5)
                        A reaction: His point is that you have to unpack the notion of fragile, which presumably cites underlying mechanisms. This is the 'virtus dormitiva' problem - but that explanation of opium's dormitive powers is not entirely stupid.
14. Science / D. Explanation / 3. Best Explanation / b. Ultimate explanation
Subatomic particles may terminate explanation, if they lack structure
                        Full Idea: The behaviour of subatomic particles cannot be further analysed into structures and this may tempt us to regard these as instances of 'brute' ungrounded dispositions which end any possible regress of explanation.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 06.4)
                        A reaction: This seems right, if it is 'structural' explanations we are after (as I think we are) which look for mechanisms. An electron seems to be just three dispositions and no structure, so there is nothing more to say. Ladyman scorns this account.
Maybe dispositions can replace the 'laws of nature' as the basis of explanation
                        Full Idea: I will consider the case for an ontology of real dispositions replacing the so-called laws of nature as the basic building blocks of explanation.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 10.1)
                        A reaction: This precisely summarises the view I am exploring, with a particular focus on real essences. I certainly think the 'laws of nature' must go. See Mumford's second book on this.
To avoid a regress in explanations, ungrounded dispositions will always have to be posited
                        Full Idea: The nature of explanation is such that ungrounded dispositions will always have to be posited in order to avoid a regress of explanation.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 10.6)
                        A reaction: This seems to be right, but leaves it open to mock the proposals as 'virtus dormitiva' - empty place-holders that ground explanations but do no explanatory work. What else can be done, though?
14. Science / D. Explanation / 4. Explanation Doubts / a. Explanation as pragmatic
Ontology is unrelated to explanation, which concerns modes of presentation and states of knowledge
                        Full Idea: Nothing about ontology is at stake in questions of explanation, for explanatory success is contingent upon the modes of presentation of explanans and explananda, and relative states of knowledge and ignorance.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 06.8)
                        A reaction: There are real facts about the immediate and unusual causes which immediately precede an event, and these might be candidates for a real explanation. There are also real mechanisms and powers which dictate a things behaviour.
26. Natural Theory / B. Natural Kinds / 4. Source of Kinds
Natural kinds, such as electrons, all behave the same way because we divide them by dispositions
                        Full Idea: Regularities exist because we classify kinds on the basis of their dispositions, not on pre-established divisions of kinds. The dispositions are the basis for the division into kinds, which is why all electrons behave in the same way.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 10.7)
                        A reaction: This strikes me as being so obvious that it is hardly worth saying, and yet an enormous number of philosophers seem to have been led up the garden path by the notion of a 'kind', probably under the influence of Kripke, Putnam and Wiggins.
26. Natural Theory / D. Laws of Nature / 1. Laws of Nature
In the 'laws' view events are basic, and properties are categorical, only existing when manifested
                        Full Idea: In the 'laws' world view, events are the basic ontological unit and properties are parasitic upon them. Properties exist only in virtue of their instantiation in events. Properties are categorical, because they are only manifested in the present.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 10.2)
                        A reaction: Mumford rejects this view, and I am with him all the way. The first requirement is that properties be active, and not inert. See Leibniz on this.
26. Natural Theory / D. Laws of Nature / 3. Laws and Generalities
Without laws, how can a dispositionalist explain general behaviour within kinds?
                        Full Idea: The problem is how, without general laws, can the dispositionalist explain why generalities in behaviour are true of kinds.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 10.3)
                        A reaction: And the answer is to make kinds depend on individuals, and not vice versa, and then point to the necessary patterns that arise from conjunctions of individual dispositions, given their identity in many individuals.
26. Natural Theory / D. Laws of Nature / 4. Regularities / a. Regularity theory
It is a regularity that whenever a person sneezes, someone (somewhere) promptly coughs
                        Full Idea: It is no doubt a true regularity that every time I sneeze, someone, somewhere in the world, immediately coughs.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 10.4)
                        A reaction: Not a huge problem for the regularity theory of laws, but the first challenge that it must meet.
Dretske and Armstrong base laws on regularities between individual properties, not between events
                        Full Idea: The improved Dretske/Armstrong regularity view of laws dispenses with the empiricist articulation of them in terms of events, and construes them as singular statements of fact that describe relations between properties.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 10.4)
                        A reaction: They then seem to go a bit mystical, by insisting that the properties are 'universals' (even if they have to be instantiated). Universals explain nothing.
26. Natural Theory / D. Laws of Nature / 8. Scientific Essentialism / b. Scientific necessity
The necessity of an electron being an electron is conceptual, and won't ground necessary laws
                        Full Idea: The logical necessity of physical laws is not required by dispositional essentialism. An electron would not be an electron if its behaviour were different from the behaviour it has in the actual world, but this necessity is purely conceptual.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 10.8)
                        A reaction: [He is particularly aiming this at Ellis and Lierse 1994] This may be missing the point. Given those electron dispositions, the electrons necessitate law-like happenings. Whether a variable entity is called an 'electron' is trivial.
26. Natural Theory / D. Laws of Nature / 8. Scientific Essentialism / d. Knowing essences
Some dispositions are so far unknown, until we learn how to manifest them
                        Full Idea: It seems reasonable to assume that there are some dispositions of some things of which we are not aware because we have not yet discovered the way to get these dispositions to manifest.
                        From: Stephen Mumford (Dispositions [1998], 03.7)
                        A reaction: This strikes me as a pretty good description of what scientists are currently doing when, for example, they build a new particle accelerator.