Ideas from 'What are Sets and What are they For?' by Oliver,A/Smiley,T [2006], by Theme Structure

[found in 'Metaphysics (Philosophical Perspectives 20)' (ed/tr Hawthorne,John) [Blackwell 2006,978-1-4051-6792-5]].

green numbers give full details    |     back to texts     |     unexpand these ideas


4. Formal Logic / F. Set Theory ST / 3. Types of Set / b. Empty (Null) Set
Maybe we can treat the empty set symbol as just meaning an empty term
                        Full Idea: Suppose we introduce Ω not as a term standing for a supposed empty set, but as a paradigm of an empty term, not standing for anything.
                        From: Oliver,A/Smiley,T (What are Sets and What are they For? [2006], 1.2)
                        A reaction: This proposal, which they go on to explore, seems to mean that Ω (i.e. the traditional empty set symbol) is no longer part of set theory but is part of semantics.
The empty set is usually derived from Separation, but it also seems to need Infinity
                        Full Idea: The empty set is usually derived via Zermelo's axiom of separation. But the axiom of separation is conditional: it requires the existence of a set in order to generate others as subsets of it. The original set has to come from the axiom of infinity.
                        From: Oliver,A/Smiley,T (What are Sets and What are they For? [2006], 1.2)
                        A reaction: They charge that this leads to circularity, as Infinity depends on the empty set.
The empty set is something, not nothing!
                        Full Idea: Some authors need to be told loud and clear: if there is an empty set, it is something, not nothing.
                        From: Oliver,A/Smiley,T (What are Sets and What are they For? [2006], 1.2)
                        A reaction: I'm inclined to think of a null set as a pair of brackets, so maybe that puts it into a metalanguage.
We don't need the empty set to express non-existence, as there are other ways to do that
                        Full Idea: The empty set is said to be useful to express non-existence, but saying 'there are no Us', or ¬∃xUx are no less concise, and certainly less roundabout.
                        From: Oliver,A/Smiley,T (What are Sets and What are they For? [2006], 1.2)
4. Formal Logic / F. Set Theory ST / 3. Types of Set / c. Unit (Singleton) Sets
The unit set may be needed to express intersections that leave a single member
                        Full Idea: Thomason says with no unit sets we couldn't call {1,2}∩{2,3} a set - but so what? Why shouldn't the intersection be the number 2? However, we then have to distinguish three different cases of intersection (common subset or member, or disjoint).
                        From: Oliver,A/Smiley,T (What are Sets and What are they For? [2006], 2.2)
5. Theory of Logic / G. Quantification / 6. Plural Quantification
If you only refer to objects one at a time, you need sets in order to refer to a plurality
                        Full Idea: A 'singularist', who refers to objects one at a time, must resort to the language of sets in order to replace plural reference to members ('Henry VIII's wives') by singular reference to a set ('the set of Henry VIII's wives').
                        From: Oliver,A/Smiley,T (What are Sets and What are they For? [2006], Intro)
                        A reaction: A simple and illuminating point about the motivation for plural reference. Null sets and singletons give me the creeps, so I would personally prefer to avoid set theory when dealing with ontology.
We can use plural language to refer to the set theory domain, to avoid calling it a 'set'
                        Full Idea: Plurals earn their keep in set theory, to answer Skolem's remark that 'in order to treat of 'sets', we must begin with 'domains' that are constituted in a certain way'. We can speak in the plural of 'the objects', not a 'domain' of objects.
                        From: Oliver,A/Smiley,T (What are Sets and What are they For? [2006], Intro)
                        A reaction: [Skolem 1922:291 in van Heijenoort] Zermelo has said that the domain cannot be a set, because every set belongs to it.
5. Theory of Logic / I. Semantics of Logic / 3. Logical Truth
Logical truths are true no matter what exists - but predicate calculus insists that something exists
                        Full Idea: Logical truths should be true no matter what exists, so true even if nothing exists. The classical predicate calculus, however, makes it logically true that something exists.
                        From: Oliver,A/Smiley,T (What are Sets and What are they For? [2006], 5.1)
6. Mathematics / A. Nature of Mathematics / 4. Using Numbers / g. Applying mathematics
If mathematics purely concerned mathematical objects, there would be no applied mathematics
                        Full Idea: If mathematics was purely concerned with mathematical objects, there would be no room for applied mathematics.
                        From: Oliver,A/Smiley,T (What are Sets and What are they For? [2006], 5.1)
                        A reaction: Love it! Of course, they are using 'objects' in the rather Fregean sense of genuine abstract entities. I don't see why fictionalism shouldn't allow maths to be wholly 'pure', although we have invented fictions which actually have application.
6. Mathematics / B. Foundations for Mathematics / 6. Mathematics as Set Theory / a. Mathematics is set theory
Sets might either represent the numbers, or be the numbers, or replace the numbers
                        Full Idea: Identifying numbers with sets may mean one of three quite different things: 1) the sets represent the numbers, or ii) they are the numbers, or iii) they replace the numbers.
                        From: Oliver,A/Smiley,T (What are Sets and What are they For? [2006], 5.2)
                        A reaction: Option one sounds the most plausible to me. I will take numbers to be patterns embedded in nature, and sets are one way of presenting them in shorthand form, in order to bring out what is repeated.