Ideas from 'Intro to Naming,Necessity and Natural Kinds' by Stephen P. Schwartz [1977], by Theme Structure

[found in 'Naming, Necessity, and Natural Kinds' (ed/tr Schwartz,Stephen P.) [Cornell 1979,0-8014-9861-9]].

green numbers give full details    |     back to texts     |     unexpand these ideas


2. Reason / D. Definition / 1. Definitions
The new view is that "water" is a name, and has no definition
                        Full Idea: Perhaps the modern view is best expressed as saying that "water" has no definition at all, at least in the traditional sense, and is a proper name of a specific substance.
                        From: Stephen P. Schwartz (Intro to Naming,Necessity and Natural Kinds [1977], §III)
                        A reaction: This assumes that proper names have no definitions, though I am not clear how we can grasp the name 'Aristotle' without some association of properties (human, for example) to go with it. We need a definition of 'definition'.
5. Theory of Logic / F. Referring in Logic / 1. Naming / b. Names as descriptive
We refer to Thales successfully by name, even if all descriptions of him are false
                        Full Idea: We can refer to Thales by using the name "Thales" even though perhaps the only description we can supply is false of him.
                        From: Stephen P. Schwartz (Intro to Naming,Necessity and Natural Kinds [1977], §III)
                        A reaction: It is not clear what we would be referring to if all of our descriptions (even 'Greek philosopher') were false. If an archaeologist finds just a scrap of stone with a name written on it, that is hardly a sufficient basis for successful reference.
The traditional theory of names says some of the descriptions must be correct
                        Full Idea: The traditional theory of proper names entails that at least some combination of the things ordinarily believed of Aristotle are necessarily true of him.
                        From: Stephen P. Schwartz (Intro to Naming,Necessity and Natural Kinds [1977], §III)
                        A reaction: Searle endorses this traditional theory. Kripke and co. tried to dismiss it, but you can't. If all descriptions of Aristotle turned out to be false (it was actually the name of a Persian statue), our modern references would have been unsuccessful.
18. Thought / C. Content / 8. Intension
The intension of "lemon" is the conjunction of properties associated with it
                        Full Idea: The conjunction of properties associated with a term such as "lemon" is often called the intension of the term "lemon".
                        From: Stephen P. Schwartz (Intro to Naming,Necessity and Natural Kinds [1977], §II)
                        A reaction: The extension of "lemon" is the set of all lemons. At last, a clear explanation of the word 'intension'! The debate becomes clear - over whether the terms of a language are used in reference to ideas of properties (and substances?), or to external items.